Summary of 'The Epistemology of Consent' by Alexander Guerrero
Alexander Guerrero’s forthcoming paper, The Epistemology of Consent, argues that philosophical debates
about consent often mistake epistemic questions about consent for metaphysical
questions, and that debates about “affirmative consent” often feature this
mistake. On Guerrero’s view, when we consider whether we ought to accept
“affirmative consent” as the standard for sexual consent, we are considering an
epistemic account about what is
required before we can either justifiably believe that someone has consented or
what is required before we can act on that belief, not a metaphysical account of when there is consent. Therefore, if we are
justified in accepting the affirmative consent standard, it will be because of
our views on epistemic justification and the relationship between
beliefs/knowledge and action. Guerrero discusses implications for two contexts:
sexual consent and consent to medical treatment. This summary will focus only
on his treatment of the former.
On the metaphysics of consent, Guerrero highlights that some
particular mental state is necessary on either the mental/attitudinal view or
the performative view. On the former view, the mental state is also sufficient
for consent—see the Metaphysics of Consent post here for more on this topic. At
least three features of the metaphysics of consent are not controversial,
argues Guerrero: consent requires a subject (the agent consenting), an object
(the state of affairs one is consenting to) and it is morally transformative
(states of affairs which were previously impermissible are made permissible
with consent). Guerrero draws our attention to two issues that arise from a
metaphysics of consent wherein an affirmative mental state is a necessary
component: the problem on “innocent recipients”, and the problem of other
minds.
Guerrero contends that those who are tempted to reject a
metaphysics of consent on which there is a necessary mental component—the “bare
performance” view – may be worried about “innocent recipients”. These are
people who receive what looks to be a valid, appropriate performance of
consent, when in fact it is not. The consent may eb the product of coercion,
for instance. In such a case, we may be tempted to say that the recipient does
nothing wrong in acting on their belief that their partner consented. Guerrero
argues that we ought to accept a distinction between culpability and wrongdoing
to explain innocent recipient cases, rather than adopt a “bare performance”
metaphysics. The following principle should help us with the innocent recipient
cases:
“Mistaken Belief: If B has a justifiable belief that A has
an attitude of affirmative endorsement toward some state of affairs, SA, then B
is not culpable for acting as if A consents to SA—even if it turns out that A
does not consent to SA, and even if this means that what B does (given that A
does not consent to SA) is objectively morally wrong”.
This still leaves us with the problem of knowing other
minds; when do we have justifiable belief that another person has the requisite
mental state? Guerrero outlines 3 categories of evidence that may help us
answer this question, these are direct testimony, indirect testimony, and other
perceptual or observational evidence. All of these classes of evidence are
defeasible, and there are also other issues we might not have considered that
complicate obtaining knowledge of consent. The following is a very brief
overview of the 5 issues that Guerrero highlights as barriers to knowing about
the mental state necessary for consent:
1.
The requisite mental state (which Guerrero
thinks is best characterized as an “attitude of affirmative endorsement”) can vary
in its details: it might be more or less emotional, vivid, transparent to the
subject, active or passive, desired, integrated into other beliefs, etc. Insofar
as this is true, we won’t have a good proxy or guide for judging whether someone
consents.
2.
It’s difficult, even for the subject that is
consenting, to know the boundaries of the object of their consent. We often
want to know what, exactly, is the state of affairs to which consent has been
given, but most of our interactions lack the formal specification of the object
of consent that we find in contracts or medical consent documents. A person may
not even have explicit views about many of the details involved in an act while
giving consent to a general act.
3.
Mental attitudes are subject to change over time;
consent can be withdrawn or altered at any moment until the relevant state of
affairs is over. To know that someone gives consent to something means to know
they consent presently.
For more on how we should understand cases where consent is withdrawn, see Dougherty’s Fickle Consent.
For more on how we should understand cases where consent is withdrawn, see Dougherty’s Fickle Consent.
4.
We might need to know about implicit attitudes. We are mostly used to thinking of consent in
terms of explicit, discrete episodes ( for example: “I do”, or signing your
name), but Guerrero contends that, as is the case for implicit beliefs, we
consent to all kinds of things all the time, without our consent to some state
of affairs being occurrent or explicit in our minds. The requisite mental state
is necessary for consent, but it may be even harder to know whether a subject
has the relevant mental state if it needn’t be occurrent in their mind.
5.
We ought to be open to the idea that consent
comes in degrees, as does the mental attitude of affirmative endorsement. Why
think that consent is a binary? It seems that I can have an attitude of tentative
endorsement – I ‘kind of’ endorse it. Do I thereby ‘kind of’ consent? Or should
we think there is a threshold for endorsement and consent exists only when we
endorse something at or above the threshold level?
The above show the difficulty and complexity of the
epistemology of consent, and given the moral significance of having this kind
of knowledge, it “complicates the epistemological story we should tell”.
Guerrero endorses two different versions of the moral encroachment thesis,
arguing that moral stakes matter. He contends that we ought to accept at least
one of:
a) Whether one is epistemically justified in believing p depends, in part, on the moral context
b) Whether it is morally objectionable to act on that justified belief depends, in part, on the moral context
This is motivated by comparing pairs of cases in which subjects have the same evidence or justifying basis for their beliefs, but the moral stakes of the actions they consider on the basis of those beliefs are different. A paraphrase of Guerrero’s example is as follows:
a) Whether one is epistemically justified in believing p depends, in part, on the moral context
b) Whether it is morally objectionable to act on that justified belief depends, in part, on the moral context
This is motivated by comparing pairs of cases in which subjects have the same evidence or justifying basis for their beliefs, but the moral stakes of the actions they consider on the basis of those beliefs are different. A paraphrase of Guerrero’s example is as follows:
Two
people, Jack and Jill, try to assess whether there are any people inside a
house. The house in fact abandoned. Jack is conducting this assessment to find
out how many people live in the town. Jill is going it to determine whether
anyone lives there because she is charged with demolishing it if it is vacant. Jack
does what he must to justifiably believe that the house is empty; he asks
neighbors, knocks on the door, peeks inside, and repeats this a week later. It’s
true that no one lives inside, so it seems plausible that Jack knows that no one lives there. Jill does
all the same things as Jack and sees no sign of anyone after making these
investigations. Has she done enough
to justifiably believe no one lives there? To know? To demolish it?
Answers to these questions will depend on one’s beliefs
about the relationship between justified belief/knowledge and justified action.
We may have good reason to think that features that are not paradigmatically
epistemic will bear on whether a subject is warranted enough to act/believe as
if some claim, p, were the case. Guerrero argues for the moral encroachment
position elsewhere; for this chapter, he highlight our common intuition that beliefs
be held with more confidence or evidential support if those beliefs are going
to be the basis for actions that have high moral stakes (eg. it might be justifiable
to form a belief based on hearsay, but think that hearsay is insufficient
grounds to punish someone).
That moral stakes matter for whether a person holds a
justified belief or can permissibly act as if they justifiably believe some
proposition has important consequences for the epistemology of consent. Many
cases in which consent is important involve high moral stakes. As a result, one
must possess more or stronger evidence to justify the belief that someone
consents, or to non-culpably act as though it were the case. Sexual consent, in
particular, according to Guerrero is a type of case in which there are high
moral stakes, and so will be a case where more or stronger evidence is
necessary. It’s hard to state generally what “more” or “stronger” evidence is
required, but Guerrero suggests that “affirmative consent” will be a good
normative standard for the epistemology of consent. Understood properly, “affirmative
consent” advocates are proposing that there be a higher bar for what counts as
sufficient evidence in cases of sexual activity to believe you have consent or
to act as though you do.
Comments
Post a Comment
Comments are moderated. Be nice.