#NotGood2Go
Rape and
sexual assault are serious, and complex, problems. In the last few years, several
consent apps—apps designed to address some of the problems of rape and sexual
assault—have garnered widespread attention. In “Could there ever be an app for
that? Consent Apps and the Problem of Sexual Assault,” John Danaher not only
criticizes the released apps, but also argues that such apps could never help to address the problems of
rape and sexual assault they aim to address.
He begins
by distinguishing between two different kinds of problems with rape and sexual
assault: ex ante and ex poste (Danaher 5). Ex ante problems are the problems that
occur before and during rape or sexual assault. So, this
category will include not just rapes and sexual assaults, but also
misunderstandings about what is needed to make sex permissible, unwillingness
to participate in awkward conversations about sex, etc. Ex poste problems are the problems that occur after rape has occurred—problems that arise with prosecuting rape
(Danaher 5). Both of these kinds of problems are crucial; efforts directed
toward ex ante problems aim to
prevent rapes from happening, while efforts directed toward ex poste problems aim to make
perpetrators face justice.
Consent
apps explicitly aim to address both ex
ante and ex poste problems of
rape and sexual assault. Generally speaking, they’re meant to both provide
resources about consent and its import, and, crucially, to make verifiable records of consent. Different apps
achieve these goals differently. Consider the app Good2Go. If Jane wants to have sex with Jill, all Jane has to do is
pull up Good2Go on her phone and hand
the phone to Jill. Jill will see the question “Are we Good2Go?”, and three
response options: “(i) ‘No, thanks’…(ii) ‘Yes…but we need to talk’ and (iii) ‘I’m
Good2Go’” (Danaher 8). If Jill selects (iii), she will be taken to another
screen where she will be asked to indicate her level of intoxication: “(i)
sober; (ii) mildly intoxicated; (iii) intoxicated but Good2Go; and (iv) pretty
wasted” (Danaher 8). If Jill selects either (i), (ii), or (iii), she will be
asked to provide her phone number, and then an encrypted record of consent will
be created. Neither Jill nor Jane would be able to access this record, but it
could be retrieved by a court order. However, if Jane selects (iv), “pretty
wasted”, she will not be allowed to signal consent. Similarly, if Jane selects “No,
Thanks” instead of “I’m Good2Go”, a message pops up reminding both parties that
“No means No!” and that ‘Yes’ can be changed to ‘No’ at any time (Danaher 8).
Danaher
begins by criticizing Good2Go’s
supposed ability to alleviate ex poste problems
(problems of prosecution). Good2Go is
meant to help with ex poste problems
by providing an unambiguous record of consent and intoxication levels. However,
Danaher thinks the records it provides are likely to be unhelpful at best, and
harmful at worst. His primary objection is that these records of consent will be
seen out of context. Without the relevant context, these recordings of consent
could be misleading (Danaher 15). Without context, coercion, deception, and
intoxication levels could all be easily obscured (Danaher 16). Thus, these
recordings of “consent” will not be
unambiguous, and they may be taken more seriously than they ought to be.
Further, the app provides no way to signal that someone has withdrawn their consent. Thus, if
someone does withdraw consent, there will only be record of their given
consent, and no record of the withdrawal (Danaher 21). This leads us to another
of Danaher’s criticisms: if victims know that there is a record of their “consent”,
they will be even less likely to want
to press charges than victims already are. Thus, this app could contribute to
the already abysmally low rate at which rapes are reported (Danaher 19).
In
addition to not solving ex poste problems,
Danaher also argues that Good2Go is
unlikely to help with ex ante problems.
Since these apps are designed to create records of consent, there will be an
unavoidable risk to privacy—while the records are encrypted, they are not un-hackable.
This will make people unlikely to use the apps. Further, Good2Go is meant to facilitate discussions about sex that people
are unlikely to have, since such conversations can be uncomfortable. However, Good2Go’s vague, euphemistic language
doesn’t actually facilitate beneficial conversations about sex, but instead
promotes more ambiguous conversations.
Danaher
thinks there could certainly be better consent apps than Good2Go (he even discusses a (slightly) better designed app, WeConsent, that I do not discuss here
because while it is better designed, it still has serious flaws). A better
designed app could use less ambiguous language and provide more nuanced options
than merely “Yes”, “No”, and “Yes, but we need to talk”. However, Danaher
thinks that these apps will necessarily stifle
conversations about sex, since they can only provide limited directions which
the conversation could go. Further, even a well-designed consent app will be
hard pressed to solve both the
decontextualization problem and the problem with privacy—in order to solve the
decontextualization problem, more context (and so more details) will be needed,
but this poses an even bigger threat to privacy. But, the fewer details are
given (and so the more privacy is protected), the more context is missing. This
leads Danaher to conclude that consent apps that create verifiable records of
consent signals—even ones that are well designed—are unlikely to address the
problems of rape and sexual assault.
Comments
Post a Comment
Comments are moderated. Be nice.