A Summary of Amia Srinivasan’s “Does anyone have the right to sex?”
In her
essay “Does Anyone have the Right to Sex?”, which appeared in the London Review
of books in March 2018, Amia Srinivasan responds to the Elliot Rodger mass
murder, a famous incel (involuntary celibate) mass murderer. Srinivasan notices
that politics and oppression is playing a role in the desire present in Rodger’s
case; for instance, Rodger desires ‘hot blonde bitches’ and sees this sort of
woman as the norm. Rodger also is incredulous that his black friend was able to
‘get’ a white girl. Srinivasan also notes, however, that an analysis of the
desire at work in the Rodger mass murder has not been present in much of the
feminist discourse regarding the murder.
An analysis
of sexual desire and the way that the political landscape creates sexual desire
is not common among the majority of feminist discourse today. Instead, liberal
feminism tends to focus on consent as that which matters when it comes to
ethical sex; consensual sex is good sex, unconsensual sex is bad sex, enough
said. Srinivasan notices a parallel between this way of thinking about sex and
the way that exchange is treated under capitalism: as Srinivasan puts it, under
capitalist free-exchange “[w]hat matters is not what conditions give rise to
the dynamics of supply and demand – why some people need to sell their labour
while others buy it – but only that both buyer and seller have agreed to the
transfer”. When this is the only consideration taken into account about the
ethics of such transactions, a great deal of exploitation is overlooked.
Srinivasan’s idea is that the same thing is true with regards to sex; when we
only take consent into account when theorizing about the ethics of sex, we
ignore the conditions that gave rise to the sex (desire and the formation of
that desire). Just as the conditions that give rise to exchange under
capitalism are unequal and unjust, so are the conditions that give rise to sexual
desire – in fact, in large part they are overlapping conditions. Without
denying that sex should be consensual, Srinivasan recommends that we
interrogate the conditions that give rise to consensual sex.
In order to
better understand why an account of the formation of sexual desire is lacking in
mainstream feminism today, Srinivasan gives a brief overview of the history of
feminist analyses of desire, beginning with an account of the theories of
Catharine MacKinnon in the 1980s. MacKinnon contested the idea that sexual
desire is primordial; she theorized that desire was created by patriarchy, a
system that dominates women. As such, domination is created as sexually
desirable, and this sort of desire is harmful for women. Those who accepted
MaKinnon’s theory of sexual desire posited the notion of a false consciousness
according to which women’s sexual desires, despite seemly their own, are
actually created by and enforced on them by patriarchal systems. Thus, women’s
perceptions of their own sexual desires as autonomous is a mistaken perception.
Against
MacKinnon, ‘pro-sex’ feminists, led by Ellen Willis, argued that the sort of
theory of desire that MacKinnon gave was harmful rather than liberating for
women. Willis argued that this sort of analysis denies women the right to
sexual pleasure, as it framed sex as something harmful for women, and furthered
the harmful idea that men want sex while women don’t really want sex but merely
put up with it. Additionally, Feminism’s move towards intersectionality compounded
the move away from MacKinnonite critiques of desire. Intersectional feminism
brought with it the conviction that no oppression under patriarchy is universal;
as such, we cannot give a universal analysis of how desire is formed under
patriarchy. Furthermore, intersectional feminists critiqued the MacKinnonite
idea of a false consciousness on the grounds that such ideas deny the autonomy
of marginalized individuals. In Srinivasan’s apt words “a feminism that trades
too freely in notions of self-deception is a feminism that risks dominating the
subjects it wants to liberate”. We might have further grounds to be suspicious
of the idea of a false consciousness when we recognize that such a notion is at
work in many rape myths (“she might have said no, but I knew by the way she was
dressed that she wanted it!”).
It is for
these reasons that analysing the formation of desire has fallen out of favour
with feminism today. Instead of examining the origins of desire, these ‘pro-sex’
feminists, who have prevailed in mainstream feminist conversation, treat desire
as a given. It is important to determine whether or not sex is consensual, but
the sexual desire that leads to sex in the first place is left unquestioned and
unjudged. At the core of this way of thinking is the fact that no one is
obligated to have sex with anyone else, and that no one is entitled to sex; one’s
desires should be respected. With this core principle Srinivasan wholeheartedly
agrees, despite the apparent tension between this thought and the idea that
sexual desire is ideologically constructed. It is with these two thoughts,
then, that Srinivasan wrestles with as she proposes that we analyse the
politics at work in the shaping of desire.
Once we
recognise that desire is, at least in part, ideologically shaped in conjunction
with the idea that no one is obligated to have sex with anyone else, and that
no one is entitled to being desired, we are left with relatively few moves left
to make. We cannot enforce equal sexual opportunity given this second
principle, yet to look at sex only through the lens of consent is to miss the
oppressive politics that work to shape sexual desire. That said, there is some
room left to maneuver: once we interrogate our own desires we might find that
those who we find most desirable are those whom our current political system most
privileges and that we find those who are disadvantaged undesirable. If we don’t
like this realisation, perhaps with the sort of intentional paradigm shifts
proposed by radical self-love movements, there is some room for us to broaden
our sexual desires.
Google Images
Thanks Shoshana, this looks like a really accurate and helpful summary.
ReplyDeleteFor anyone who may want to read the full piece, it is here: https://www.lrb.co.uk/v40/n06/amia-srinivasan/does-anyone-have-the-right-to-sex
Free registration is required to access it via that link.
Thanks for adding this Jonathan! It just occurred to me today that I should add the link, but now I see that it's already been done.
Delete